PEPC LIBRARY

Hélène Aji
Université du Maine ( France)

“Writing (as) (and) thinking”:
Charles Bernstein’s Work “in” Language

This essay was first published in Études Anglaises LIX 3 (July-September 2006) 341-355. Used with the permission of the author and publisher. © Hélène Aji 2006

Summary:
Taking up the tension between poetry and philosophy, this article traces the way the poetics of American Language poet Charles Bernstein redefines the domains of these two modes of discourse, and demonstrates how they share a common medium, a common ground, and common issues. By erasing generic differences and questioning stylistic decisions, Bernstein proves to be not so much a poet of grammar or a mechanic of syntax as a “technician of the human.”

Résumé:
Partant de la tension existant entre poésie et philosophie, cet article analyse comment la poétique de Charles Bernstein, Language Poet américain, redéfinit les domaines de ces deux modes de discours et démontre qu’ils ont en commun un medium, un terrain et des enjeux. Quand il efface les différences entre les genres et interroge les choix stylistiques, Bernstein se révèle non tant comme poète de la grammaire ou mécanicien de la syntaxe que comme “technicien de l’humain.”

———

In the opening sentences of his article entitled “Thought’s Measure,” Charles Bernstein makes a distinction between conventional modes of thinking about the circulation of meaning as through language, and its reformulation in terms of “think[ing] and writ[ing] in language” (Content’s Dream 61). If language is a medium, according to Bernstein, it is not the medium of our hermeneutic attempts, the medium through which we convey meanings about the world and our experience. Rather and more radically, it could be the medium through which “we experience the world” (Content’s Dream 61), thus an epistemological tool–or an impediment. Such reflection on the very functioning of language is not entirely new to the domain of poetry and poetics, although it seems to become more and more central as the Modernist experience unfolds and as poets, once free of the constraints of metrics, focus on the materiality of language. The shift from the commitment to the spoken, which was at the origins of the questioning of metrics, to a commitment to the quiddity of words, beyond or beside their visual dimension, is at stake in the so-called linguistic turn.

With Gertrude Stein, Charles Bernstein (although he is not the only one in this) calls attention to the combinatory nature of language and to the potentialities of deviant combinations to increase the awareness of the conventional in conventions, of the limitations enforced by the criteria of legibility and intelligibility. With Ludwig Wittgenstein, Bernstein integrates the idea that thought advances in language and that the borders of the conceivable coincide with the frontiers of the sayable.

                                                                      &
poetry does have a mission to be as powerful as
the strongest drug, to offer a vision-in-sound
to compete with the world we know so that we can find
the worlds we don’t. But we don’t
in fact escape ideology: no other
perhaps not even different: but an alternate point
of perspective, a supplemental attentional
focus/unfocus. Paradise, as hell,
inheres: there are not limits that language cannot
reach.
(Bernstein “Artifice of Absorption” [1992] 76)

This, however, does not preclude the persistence, and resistance, of an unsayable (also inconceivable), but it opens the door to experiments in language that would push back the limits of the sayable, thanks to an expansion, and transgression, of the syntactically acceptable. Thus the poetic mode of the (Steinian) enigmatic proposition comes to meet the (Wittgensteinian) philosophical mode of the aphorism, on the common ground of a (Bernsteinian) reflexive poem. Consequently, “littérature et philosophies mêlées,” the subtitle of the 1975 issue of Poétique, might need qualifying: mixing or blending literature and philosophy together implies an original heterogeneity, with its subsequent possibilities for “hybridization” (Starobinski Poétique 8), for “inclusion” (notably the inclusion of literature into philosophy–Lacoue-Labarthe Poétique 81: “la fiction et la figure appartiennent à la philosophie et lui ont toujours appartenu”), for a “dialogue” between different “genres” (Lacoue-Labarthe et Nancy Poétique 148). What if one came to consider that, since they both work “in” language, literature and philosophy are not generically distinct, that their differentiation stems from differing modes of reading, that both evidence pragmatic attempts or experiments to push back the limits of the sayable, taking chances with the reader and running the risk of the illegible, that being in language cannot be confined either to the aesthetic or to the ethic, but is a mode of inhabiting one and the same world–ours?

Différance

So to return briefly and allusively to Jacques Derrida’s distinction between différence and différance, one is tempted to appropriate the idea of a process of differentiation, at work in the separation between philosophy and poetry–and one is also tempted to question it. With Charles Bernstein, the difference between the two is to be abolished: there are not two languages, one which would be the language of philosophy and the other that would be the language of poetry, one voicing the disquisitions of the rational subject as the other leaves free rein to the divagations of the lyrical self. Such positioning stems directly from the teachings of Stanley Cavell whose classes Bernstein attended at Harvard, so that Bernstein’s reflections as he is “reading Cavell reading Wittgenstein” emerge as both a summary of these teachings and the formulation of their relevance to his own poetics. By focusing notably on The Claim of Reason, Bernstein situates his thinking in a context in which reason does not only have claims but also in which reason could be claimed... by poetry for instance. Repeatedly what is to be subverted is what I would call dichotomic thinking, and which Bernstein defines as “schismatic” thinking:

In the opening pages of The Claim of Reason, Stanley Cavell points to the splitting of the philosophical tradition of the West into a British and American mode and a Continental mode as somehow analogous to the split within our own (one) culture between philosophy and literature. That these schisms everywhere inform Cavell’s work signals an appreciation that for him they are emblematic of even deeper recurring schisms in the fabric of human life and our conceptions of it, of feeling (or being) split off from a world which we are wholly inside of. Cavell’s work, it seems to me, is largely absorbed with giving an accounting of these schisms; his sense of what constitutes an account is, for me; the place where he is able to occupy a ground held in common by both philosophy and literature. (Bernstein “The Objects of Meaning: Reading Cavell Reading Wittgenstein” [1986] 166)

Significantly, the common ground between philosophy and literature, which, according to Bernstein, Cavell would occupy is a place to account for (not generate) “schisms,” that are the expression not so much of our “being” separated from our world as of our “feeling” separated from it. Such assessment of Cavell’s philosophical activity is of course not limited to Cavell, and has major consequences on the way we think of philosophy as related to literature: our method of thinking can be identified with a method of “splitting” or differentiating and it can be recognized equally as we produce what we hold to be philosophical discourse and as we produce literary (poetic, fictional) discourse. What Bernstein here calls for is to transcend generic splittings so that our activity in language can be recognized and evaluated. We are not dealing with the proliferation of codes that need finer and finer analyses and specifications, and their corollary aspirations to (impossible) unity and general communication. Rather, these paradoxically more and more specific generalizations prevent us from seeing and appreciating the “shared grammar” residing not in the plurality of languages but in the common use of language.

The lesson of metaphysical finitude is not that the world is just codes and as a result presence is to be ruled out as anything more than nostalgia, but that we can have presence, insofar as we are able, only through a shared grammar. (Bernstein “The Objects of Meaning: Reading Cavell Reading Wittgenstein” [1986] 182)

Bernstein’s reading of Cavell induces at the same time a reconsideration of philosophy neither as fiction and poetry (which would be just an inversion of Lacoue-Labarthe’s remark which triggered this reflection) nor, but it seems obvious now, as an annexation of literature as a privileged (or unprivileged, at that) object of philosophy.

While this implies different language practices, and an emphasis on the “how” rather than the “what” of both philosophy and poetry, which is not limited to a questioning of the “referential fallacy” of language (Perloff 162), it also opens up onto a redefinition of the objectives of philosophy and of poetry, as identical objectives. The differentiation between the two can be shown as the result of social and professional distinctions, that are emanations from “a tradition of thinking and writing, and a social matrix of publications, professional associations, audience” (Bernstein in Silliman [1986] 583). This line of reasoning leads to an inquiry into the “social meaning of specific modes of discourse” (Bernstein in Silliman [1986] 583) and to an incitation to the writer–and to the reader:

To literally put words into Merleau-Ponty’s mouth:
The thickness of writing between
the reader & the poem is constitutive for the poem
of its visibility & for the reader
of the outer limit of his or her absorption
in the poem; it is not an obstacle
between them, it is their means
of communication. The thickness of writing,
far from rivaling that of the world,
is on the contrary the sole
means it has to go to the heart of things
by making itself part
of the material world, absorbed
by it.
(Bernstein “Artifice of Absorption” [1992] 87)

As the writer is to remove himself from the constraining frame of “normal” modes of writing, he is also to produce texts that will force the reader to distance himself from the conventional circumstances of reading, assuming that the form of one given discourse, “the order of [its]elements,” is “value constituting and indeed experience engendering, and therefore always at issue, never assumable” (Bernstein in Silliman [1986] 586).

If philosophy is to be characterized as a form consisting of clearly exposited arguments whose appeal is to the logic of validity, then it would systematically be limited by the limits of expository practice. I don’t think it makes sense to restrict philosophy to this particular mode of discourse, both because it would rule out some of the best work in philosophy and because it suggests that reason’s most “clear” expression is exposition. Rather it seems to me that, as a mode, contemporary expository writing edges close to being merely a style of decorous thinking, rigidified and formalized to a point severed from its historical relation to method in Descartes and Bacon. It is no longer an enactment of thinking or reasoning but a representation (and simplification) of an 18 th century ideal of reasoning. And yet the hegemony of its practice is rarely questioned outside certain poetic and philosophic contexts. On this level, I would characterize as sharing a political project both a philosophical practice and a poetic practice that refuse to adopt expository principles as their basic claim to validity. (Bernstein in Silliman [1986] 586)

As Bernstein follows on in a fairly well-known fashion by opposing the writing of Montaigne to that of Descartes (Bernstein in Silliman [1986] 587), the strong ties between a refusal to differentiate between the domains of philosophy and poetry and a particular form of political protest come to the fore. In his close analysis of Bernstein 1992 collection of texts (for it is difficult to classify them as poems or essays, as essays in the form of poems or as poems in the form of essays), Bob Perelman links the double choice of the collection’s title (a p o e t i c s) and of including “Artifice of Absorption” to Bernstein’s own definition and approach to poetry. And this definition is poetic, philosophical and political, as if these three terms which we distinguish out of necessity were in fact referring to one and the same thing.

A small typographical feature can serve as an initial symptom. On the front and back covers, the half-title and title pages, and in the paragraph giving the Library of Congress publication data, the book’s title is A Poetics. But on one page before the text begins, a p o e t i c s is printed in evenly spaced lowercase bold letters. This doppelganger embodies a key property of the book: a p o e t i c s with its nonhierarchical typography (no capital letters, no word boundaries) is a small sample of the radically democratic poetry Bernstein is arguing for, a poetry not governable by a normative poetics, a poetry that would itself constitute an apoetics. (Perelman [1996] 80)

As a “paradigmatic text [...] since it flaunts in its very composition the impossibility of separating the text from its theory” (Cazé 96), “Artifice of Absorption” underlines the fact that an “apoetics” is not an “anti-poetics” though. It is not simply the opposition to a poetics, given, conventional and to be stigmatized. Rather it is a pointer to a poetics that is not the absence of a poetics (a non-poetics, without rules or criteria) but to a poetics that remains aware of the possibility of that absence or lack, which constantly totters on the brink of dissolving itself into “apoetics” because it is taking into account the provisional dimension of its fixities. Thus if “Bernstein claims poetry as the prime theoretical instrument” (Perelman [1996] 80) and if the Bernsteinian text is essentially a “a hybrid text” (Cazé 96), this is just one moment of his poetry, one form, one “mode” to use a characteristically Bernsteinian term. The issue is indeed “to avoid self-definition or be convicted of the violence of generalization” (Perelman [1996] 85) but it is not merely to the expense of genre, as Perelman puts it:

To avoid this violence, stability of genre is sacrificed. The excerpt could be poetry, prose, or neither. It looks like poetry but the rhetoric and subject are expository, and the line breaks are insignificant. Such blurring is the point [...]. (Perelman [1996] 85)

Not poetry as the vehicle for theory, then, nor poetry as a mix of genres, nor poetry as the genre to put an end to generic distinctions, and yet Bernstein’s poetry does do all this. So the line breaks, for instance, are not “insignificant,” but as Perelman himself qualifies it, they “seem deliberately nonsignificant” (Perelman [1996] 89), which makes them all the more significant. Thus in this excerpt from “Artifice of Absorption”:

It is just my insistence
that poetry be understood as epistemological
inquiry; to cede meaning would be to undercut
the power of poetry to reconnect us
with modes of meaning given in language
but precluded by the hegemony of restricted
epistemological economies (an hegemony that moves
toward the negation of nondominant restricted
economies as much as repressing the asymptotic
horizon of the unrestricted economies. As
(Bernstein “Artifice of Absorption” [1992] 17-18)

One could comment on every run-on-line as it sustains the argument unfolded in a dominantly expository sentence. The gap between “insistence” and the proposition that develops it corresponds to the pause which emphatically marks the moment of assertion and unveiling; the movement from the epithet “epistemological” to the noun “inquiry” is to be made over a gap that conventionally separates poetry not so much from the adventure of epistemology but from the systematicity of scientific investigation. Further down the variation, around the line break, between “restricted / epistemological economies” and “restricted / economies”, underlines the loss of the “epistemological” dimension, thus effecting a deeper undermining of these dominant economies, as well as providing the possibility for an extension of meaning that would be “unrestricted” to “epistemological economies.” As a matter of fact, the line breaks do not merely allow for the shaping of prose into poetry, in a formal cutting-up that might remind some of the worst attempts at free verse, but perform a pacing of discourse that breaks down the monolithic quality of argumentation and opens up the gaps necessary to reflection and interpretation. In this respect, Bernstein’s poem does not only attempt to fight on the battle field of theory while artificially keeping its poetic “disguise” (Perelman [1996] 89), but it becomes the very embodiment of a criticism of norm–and form.

And this is also where poetry and philosophy compete, carrying on a project of investigation through means and modes that are conventionally conceived of as different, but only when conforming with a convention which demands questioning:

Indeed if one takes it to be the primary philosophical problem–many philosophers of course do not–that the description (ontology) of events, persons, experience, objects, etc. are at issue, and it is not just a question of axiomitizing types of these things, then the forms of art not only “define the structure of human experience” as Kuhn has it but investigate the terms of human experience and their implications. The poetry and philosophy share the project of investigating the possibilities (nature) and structures of phenomena. (Bernstein in Silliman [1986] 585)

As Bernstein borrows from Descartes the emphasis not on the results of investigation so much as on the method of investigating, he conceptualizes a trend latent in 20 th-century poetry which insists on the commitment to the process of creation rather than on its final object. However, in this specific case, the insistence on process leads to an exploration outside the boundaries of one mode, not taking another as its object but taking itself as its own object. This is what he comes to call a “constructive writing practice,” a term which Barrett Watten also uses in his characterization of contemporary, reflexive and political, experiments in poetry.

Indeed much “normal” philosophy and poetry simply adopts a style and works on techniques within it, without considering either the implications of the larger modality or its methodological assumptions. On the other hand, a “constructive” mode would suggest that the mode itself is explored as content, its possibilities of meaning are investigated and presented, and that this process is itself recognized as a method.

One vision of a “constructive” writing practice I have, and it can be approached in both poetry and philosophy, is of a multi-discourse text, a work that would involve many different types and styles and modes of language in the same “hyperspace”. Such a textual practice would have a dialogic or polylogic rather than monologic method. (Bernstein in Silliman [1986] 590-591)

Polylogism, if one may use the term, implies for Bernstein the use of punning or the play on orthography, or the recourse to impersonation, constructing the poetic voice as a voice other than the poet’s but still sending us back wonderingly to the poet and the world we share with him. It is this poetic practice, in which the poet becomes a “technician of the human” (Bernstein “Stray Straws and Straw Men” in Andrews [1984] 40), which turns Bernstein’s poetics into a pragmatics, radicalizing the Objectivist notion of the poem as object:

10. Compare / these two views / of what poetry / is.
     In the one, an instance (a recording perhaps) of reality / fantasy / experience / event is presented to us through the writing.
     In the other, the writing itself is seen as an instance of reality / fantasy  / experience / event.
(Bernstein “Stray Straws and Straw Men” in Andrews [1984] 41)

Pragmatics

In the aphorisms which make up “Stray Straws and Straw Men,” Charles Bernstein makes at least two important claims: a claim for “technical precision” (Bernstein “Stray Straws and Straw Men” in Andrews [1984] 40), and the claim to write “manifestation[s] of using a full-blown language” that are fully calculated and premeditated (Bernstein “Stray Straws and Straw Men” in Andrews [1984] 43). The underlying statement bridges the gap between the expository or rational and the poetic or lyrical. It implies a denial of the poetic claim to a natural, uncontrived, mode of self-expression, which has become the trademark of some poets of orality. Bernstein does not however lay a claim to radical impersonality in poetry, thus qualifying the High Modernist motto, but he reassesses the poem and its function, stressing intentionality.

18. There is no natural look or sound to a poem. Every element is intended, chosen. That is what makes a thing a poem. Modes cannot be escaped, but they can be taken for granted. They can also be meant.

[...] It is natural that there are modes but there is no natural mode. (Bernstein “Stray Straws and Straw Men” in Andrews [1984] 44-45)

Paraphrasing the famous words of Charles Olson and Robert Creeley over and over again (on another instance in “Artifice of Absorption,” see Cazé 95-96), Bernstein is not afraid of contradiction, since it is in contradiction that the very instability of thinking and of writing can be approached. How can one reconcile the following statements, which were published in the same ground-breaking volume edited by Ron Silliman, In the American Tree?

Theory is never more than the extension of practice [...]. (Bernstein in Silliman [1986] 488)

All writing is a demonstration of method; it can assume a method or investigate it. In this sense, style and mode are always at issue, for all styles are socially mediated conventions open to reconvening at any time. (Bernstein in Silliman [1986] 589)

Perhaps they can be reconciled through the very notion of “conventions open to reconvening,” in the sense that all statements would remain open to restating, all writings open to rewriting, etc. This insistence on the exploratory nature of writing itself (writing as thinking) is not unique to Bernstein: it can be found in statements by Lyn Hejinian (“The language itself materializes thought; the writing realizes ideas. One discovers what one thinks, sees, says, and as the words unfold in the work, the work, directed by form, extends outward.”–Hejinian in Silliman [1986] 487). Similarly, Bernstein shares with Nick Piombino the idea that “poetry is a graphic form of unrighting the publicly codified colocation of a grapheme with symbolized ordinary writing and speech usage and the imaging function of the mind” (Piombino in Silliman [1986] 577).

The aim of poetic practice, then, is not to use “artifice” to erase the markers of self-expression, since writing remain a “trace of a self” (Bernstein in Silliman [1986] 593), nor is it just to “characterize the characterizations” at work in the writing (Bernstein in Perelman [1985] 20), in a typological investigation reminiscent of the categories of normative philosophy, but it is to “recreate” the conditions of the experience of reading and in so doing make it a palpable experience:

All of which are ways of releasing the energy inherent in the referential dimension of language, that these dimensions are the material of which the writing is made, define its medium. Making the structures of meaning in language more tangible and in that way allowing for the maximum resonance for the medium–the traditional power that writing has always had to make experience palpable not by simply pointing to it but by (re)creating its conditions. (Bernstein “Semblance” in Andrews [1984] 115)

In this respect, Bernstein’s poetics is not against or outside tradition, and it does not have the ambition of earlier Modernist attempts to found a new tradition for a new poem. It is inscribed in language, in a tradition made present through the exhibition of its methods (not through the enforcement of one method made imperceptible through continuous conformity). Not so paradoxically then, the heterogeneity of Bernstein’s poetic modes is the direct consequence of a homogeneous effort to evidence the process of destabilization and to create the need for the reader to work at balancing the unbalanced in an exaggeration of the commonplace act of reading. When reading perforce becomes deciphering, in the case of unorthographic texts, or more simply in the case of expository discourse presented as lineated poetry, the very practice of reading is experienced as what it is: the hazardous piecing together of disrupted elements according to fragile and possibly inadequate preconceived structures.

These
textual
dynamics
can
be
thought
about
in
relation
to
the
reader
&
to
the
structure
of
the
poem.
(Bernstein “Artifice of Absorption” [1992] 30)

The recourse to these structures is unavoidable, but the awareness of their shortcomings is not necessarily foregrounded. In Bernstein’s work, one thus finds several examples of these apparently “strong statements,” which under our own eyes “begin to destabilize like a radioisotope” (Bernstein in Perelman [1985] 28). It is the commentary Antoine Cazé makes of a similar passage in “Artifice of Absorption”:

Here, the poetic shape in which theoretical discourse is cast, parodying the artifice of lineation, only folds poetry back onto poetic theory just when it seemed to make it possible for the former to subvert the latter. But the reverse is equally true [...]. (Cazé 102)

“Not this. / What then?”(Silliman [2002] 16): the leitmotif of Ron Silliman’s long procedural poem Tjanting could be taken up as a description of the iterated impulse governing the production of interpretations of Bernstein’s texts. Interpretation is not to be checkmated in Bernstein though, but it is to be shown as plural, contradictory, multi-directional and eventually unstable. This is part and parcel of the poet’s fundamental intention:

I don’t think I manage to achieve as many different interpretations as I might like. [laughter] I’m very much limited by what makes sense to me, because of this horribly mistaken but nonetheless ongoing concern for the poem to sound right. I have a desire for an infinitely negative capability, and yet I am always coming upon very concrete forms of stabilization, characterization, that make patterns in respect to one another, which is what you notice at the level of this book

So there’s a desire to push things as far as they will go and the recognition that it doesn’t go all that far. But if you don’t push, you don’t even find out the most obvious relations, the most obvious meanings. The process, to call it destabilization is itself false, ends up creating these tightly woven, webbed formations.

But you say I get at this by irony and distortion. Now, distortion, that’s one thing... but I’ve never operated with irony. [laughter] Comedy yes, schticks is more my... (Bernstein in Perelman [1985] 29)

The trajectory which Bernstein outlines from the limited plurality of interpretations (and his fantasized infinite movement of interpretation) to the use of humor, rather than irony, at the same time takes us back to the refusal of “monoplanar or dyadic movement” (Bernstein in Perelman [1985] 20), which was identified as a poetic and philosophical posture, and propels us toward an evaluation of his often comic (and consequently often denigrated) poetry. Contrary to common assumptions, Bernstein’s poetic body is varied and is not massively theoretical, in the sense of what was said here about “Artifice of Absorption.” In fact, “Artifice of Absorption” itself exhibits moments of comic relief–or is it more disturbing moments of comicity? Indeed where irony still functions within the frame of conventional readings, the comic in poetry, a comic that would not convey a stable anti-discourse underlying what is apparently stated but undermined, entails radical reconfigurations of reader expectation and reader response. As Bernstein argues his choice of humor over irony, one comes to understand his very practice of non-choice, non-mastery, and instability in language:

My problem with irony is that it is set-up in which the “real” meaning is the opposite of the surface meaning. X equals not X. It’s just another binary system, like the ambiguity in a drawing of a duck that can also be read as the drawing of a rabbit. It’s the difference between a double entendre and Joycean word play. Irony is simple ambiguity: ironic/iconic. What I want is humor that opens out into a multivolitional field destabilizing to any fixed meaning that can be assigned and that persists out of context. [...] Humor as destabilizing not only the negation to mean affirmation but the affirmation also–the idea of a perpetual motion machine that never stops pinging and ponging off the walls, ceilings, floors. So returns to... let’s say “the absolute,” maybe the ineffable–everywhere said, nowhere stated. (Bernstein in Perelman [1985] 30)

The comic does not work at undermining the seriousness of the conventionally poetic, and it does not aim at entertaining–although as a reader one might think it is an attractive side-effect... Nevertheless it is central to Bernstein’s poetry that the comic should not stop at that, that it should not stop at all, actually.

Such poetic play [acting out, in dialectical play, the insincerity of form as much as content] does not open into a neat opposition of dry high irony and wet lyric expressiveness but, in contrast, collapses into a more destabilizing field of pathos, the ludicrous, schtick, sarcasm; a multidimensional textual field that is congenitally unable to maintain an evenness of surface tension or a flatness of affect, where linguistic shards of histrionic inappropriateness pierce the momentary calm of an obscure twist of phrase, before cantoring into the next available trope; less a shield than a probe. (Bernstein “Comedy and the Poetics of Political Form” [1992] 220)

To take but one example, the poem entitled and beginning “Dear Mr. Fanelli” might first seem to be the lineated transcription of a customer’s letter to complain about the state of disrepair of New York’s 79th Street subway station:

I saw your picture
in the 79th street
station. You said
you’d be interested
in any comments I
might have on the condition of the
station. Mr. Fanelli,
there is a lot of
debris in the 79th street
station that makes it
unpleasant to wait in
for more than a few
minutes. The station
could use a paint
job and maybe
new speakers so you
could understand
the delay announcements
that are always being
broadcast. Mr.
Fanelli–
                                   (Bernstein “Dear Mr. Fanelli,” [1999] 58)

As the poem unfolds, the reader could be more and more convinced that lineation is arbitrary and that the text is an actual letter to the picture posted in the station, a letter that evinces some superficial compassion for commuters and for the homeless who live in the station, minor preoccupation with the maintenance of the station and the running of trains, and a more disquieting, almost pathological need to establish personal communication with someone who might turn out to be something, the product of an adman (the commercial writer Bernstein used to be) to pacify the public. As the poem begins though, one can also construct a reflection on line breaks, in the same way as could be done for “Artifice of Absorption”: on the third line, “you said” lends a voice to the picture (or is it just the caption which is turned into speech, thus emphasizing the impact of the written as spoken?); on the fifth line, with “comments I,” and the I suspended at the end of the line, the poetic voice is visually isolated and foregrounded (yet its closeness to the term “comments” allied to the disrupting elision of the relative leads the reader to wonder about the I as commenting instance); “on the condition of the” precludes the expected “on the condition of man,” but it also rings very much like it, with a twist; at the end of our quotation, the separation between “Mr.” and “Fanelli” calls into question the politeness of the interjection (“mister” alone is condescending after all), as well as the social organization that constructs Mr.-Fanellis. After four pages of this, as the poem winds down, the offer of meeting over lunch or after work, ends the poem, very much unlike a letter with the following two-liner:

Think about it, Mr.
Fanelli.
                                    (Bernstein “Dear Mr. Fanelli,” [1999] 62)

The abruptness and concision disrupts the apparently free flow of remarks that preceded, creates the comic effect the ridiculous offer first triggers, but it also somehow fails to ring that funny, and the injunction to think, about an “it” that could be other than just lunch or drinks, with the return of the splitting of the addressee’s name, sounds like a warning, maybe a threat. With Mr. Fanelli, then, we are “absorbed,” integrated, into a web of language that threatens to smother us and leave us speechless. What joy (or enjoyment) is there in this? Very little but for the relief provided by naming, locating, and the more general use of the commonplace, to instill a less commonplace and more disturbing doubt about human relations and the world we live in.

As one moves along to consider other texts, such as Legend, a text written, among other things, to destabilize the authorial figure by Andrews, Bernstein, DiPalma, McCaffery and Silliman, or Veil, a palimpsestic text of superimposed pages made hardly legible but kept decipherable so that reading becomes a painful exercise in peering and eye-crossing, one sees how Bernstein’s “apoetics” is indeed a pragmatics: Legend “stages the undoing of its utopia even as it is being constructed” (Watten 79), whereas “the poems in Veil are surprising less for their illegibility than for their ultimate intelligibility” (Dworkin 53).

Specifically, Veil amplifies the sense of bodily presence in a specific environment: the precise distance and angle of the book, the gentle curve of the page–suddenly so three-dimensional–as it arcs from its binding towards the hand holding it at the edge, and every tremor of that hand, and the shadow it casts, and the shading of the pages’ center fold, the quality of the light source and its angle of incidence, its reflection or refraction from a chemically sized sheet, halation, the weave of its paper and the sheen of its ink, the wavering of heated air, the breeze from a window, a passing shadow, motes. (Dworkin 57)

All of them signal writing and reading as modes of thinking, but also as modes of living, infinite as being persists and finite as the end of our efforts looms in the not so far distance. The trembling of the hand which Craig Dworkin alludes to is a trembling of a human being, just as the laughter Bernstein resorts to is a postponement of and a way to the ineffable and unbearable–“his” way.

(A)e(s)th(et)ics: an end and a beginning

Just as Charles Bernstein’s poems construct deviant experiences of language as part of our world experience, calling for variant and questioning readings, they inscribe themselves in a practice that is its own theory, a poetry that is philosophy, or at least that inhabits the same terrain as philosophy in its quests for alternative “models of truth and meaning not dependent for their power on the dominant structures” (Bernstein in Silliman [1986] 588):

The question is always: what is the meaning of this language practice; what values does it propagate; to what degree does it encourage an understanding, a visibility, of its own values or to what degree does it repress that awareness? To what degree is it in dialogue with the reader and to what degree does it command or hypnotize the reader? Is its social function liberating or repressive? Such questions of course open up into much larger issues than ones of aesthetics per se, open the door by which aesthetics and ethics are unified. (Bernstein in Silliman [1986] 589)

Because of his commitment to a poetics that is a pragmatics, Bernstein comes to contradict the Deleuzian notion of “deterritorialization”, because “everything exists within material, historical situations, within contexts [and] there’s nothing wrong with territorializations or characterizations, if we understand them to be provisional contextualizations” (Bernstein in Perelman [1985] 17). By dismantling the conventions of syntax or by cutting up the prosaic into free-verse lines, Bernstein investigates rather than opposes the standards by which we write and think: poetry does it, but so does philosophy.

Indeed in its counterconventional investigations, poetry engages public language at its roots, in that it tests the limits of conventionality while forging alternate conventions (which, however, need not seek to replace other conventions in quest of becoming new standards). Moreover, the contained scale of such poetic engagements allows for a more comprehensive understanding of the formation of public space: of polis. (Bernstein “Comedy and the Poetics of Political Form” [1992] 219)

Since we think and write in language (and not through language), since language is not simply the means but the sole locus of our impressions and expressions, the very notion of medium, as a mode of conveyance, collapses, in such a way that language becomes a place for the subject to inhabit and whose limits or boundaries he is meant to test repeatedly. What does this tell us about our existence? Or at least about some conceptions of our existence?

As Charles Bernstein’s writing as thinking and thinking as writing move from his essays to the poems and to his recent opera libretto Shadowtime on the life and works of Walter Benjamin, there emerges a sort of “ideolect” to take up his own coinage (Bernstein "Poetics of the Americas" [1999] 113), which Barrett Watten discusses in The Constructivist Moment (177): not only can (or should or does) the poem think, but it is thinking, i.e. made of the same stuff as thought, it is thinking itself. But as Bernstein returns to Cavell reading Wittgenstein there appears a wondering that opens the poetic and the philosophical to the mystical:

If we are to live the “truths of skepticism,” one of them is the mystery that the world exists [Cavell 234]. It is to this truth that literature can speak–of the wonder of the world being at all, and its being “so,” as is. [...] Though we may recoil from the world, its facts and its responsibilities, and the world itself may seem to retreat from us, the presence of the world, still, as by magic, awaits. (Bernstein “The Objects of Meaning: Reading Cavell Reading Wittgenstein” [1986] 183)


Works cited:

Andrews, Bruce and Charles Bernstein, eds. The L=A=N=G=U=A=G=E Book. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1984.
Andrews, Bruce; Bernstein, Charles; DiPalma, Ray; McCaffery, Steven; Silliman, Ron. Legend. New York: L=A=N=G=U=A=G=E/Segue, 1980.
Bernstein, Charles. A Poetics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1992.
Bernstein, Charles. Content’s Dream. Los Angeles: Sun & Moon, 1986.
Bernstein, Charles. My Way. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1999.
Bernstein, Charles. Shadowtime. Los Angeles: Green Integer, 2005.
Bernstein, Charles. Veil. Madison: Xeroxial Editions, 1987.
Cavell, Stanley. The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein, Skepticism, Morality, and Tragedy. New York: Oxford University Press, 1979.
Cazé, Antoine. “Margins of Theory, Theory of Margins.” Delville, Michel and Pagnoulle, Christine, eds. Mechanics of the Mirage: Postwar American Poetry. Liège: Liège Language and Literature, English Department, Université de Liège, 2000. 93-105.
Dworkin, Craig. Reading the Illegible. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2003.
Perelman, Bob, ed. Writing/Talks. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1985.
Perelman, Bob. The Marginalization of Poetry: Language Writing and Literary History. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996.
Perloff, Marjorie. Differentials: Poetry, Poetics, Pedagogy. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press, 2004.
Poétique 21 (1st quarter 1975), 175 pp. Edited by Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe. Paris: Seuil, 1975. Articles by Michel Deguy, Jacques Derrida, Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe, Jean-Luc Nancy, Jean Starobinski.
Silliman, Ron, ed. In the American Tree. Orono: National Poetry Foundation, 1986.
Silliman, Ron. Tjanting (1981). Cambridge: Salt, 2002.
Watten, Barrett. The Constructivist Moment: From Material Text to Cultural Poetics. Middletown: Wesleyan University Press, 2003.